Journal of Scientific Exploration, Vol. 20, No. 3, pp. 421-427, 2006
ESSAY
The Two-Edged Sword of Skepticism:
Occam's Razor and Occam's Lobotomy
Henry Bauer
Dean Emeritus of Arts
& Sciences, Professor Emeritus of Chemistry & Science Studies,
Virginia Polytechnic Institute
& State University
e-mail: hhbauer@ vt. edu
Abstract-Skepticism views the probability of a proposition as always less than
1, whereas belief or disbelief are absolute, asserting that the probability equals
1 or 0.
The proper spirit of skepticism is constructive: it seeks to improve knowledge
by stimulating better estimates of probability. That means micro-skepticism,
questioning the soundness of every detail of fact, method, logic; it is empirical.
By contrast, macro-skepticism is deductive; it relies on current scientific knowledge,
which makes it backward-looking and destructively critical rather than
constructively critical. It appeals commonly to Occam's Razor: it is always
"simplest" to explain things in the way we are used to doing. But knowledge
advances through change; so the Razor becomes a Lobotomy as people forget
Einstein's insistence that theories should be as simple as possible, but no simpler.
Strong skepticism about new claims safeguards science against error. But the
failure to maintain skepticism after a theory has been incorporated fosters
dogmatism. There are a mounting number of contemporary examples where the
native conservatism and dogmatism of science have become tyranniesknowledge
monopolies and research cartels-because science has become so
much governed by official bureaucracies.
Keywords: skepticism-Occam's Razor
I was asked to talk about the
benefits of skepticism in science; partly as a
Press.
counterweight to the unappealing practices of self-styled "skeptics" organizations,
which bring the notion of skepticism into bad repute; but also because true
skepticism is so necessary for us who are interested in taking serious anomalous
claims seriously. Since
I agree wholeheartedly with these aims, I said, "Yes",
without really thinking about it. But when
I started to write some notes, I realized
that there's nothing to be said, because the benefits of skepticism are so obvious.
That reminded me, as it often does, of T.
G. Room, professor of pure mathematics
at the University of Sydney. He was working a proof for us in class, and was saying,
"And it is obvious that
. . .". Then he paused. He stood back, looked at what he'd
written on the chalk-board, mumbled, "But is it obvious?" He turned back to us and
said, "I'll be back in a few minutes", and he left the room. When he came back, he
was smiling. He said, "Yes, it's obvious", and continued with the rest of the proof.
Nothing should really be taken as obvious until one has given it some thought. The
reason skepticism in science is obviously beneficial is this: It's quite unlikely that we
already know everything that is to be known. Therefore, some of what we now know
is wrong, if only through being incomplete. But we don't know exactly what part of
what we now believe is wrong, and we certainly don't know in what way it's wrong.
So skepticism is the only intellectually justifiable approach. It is one of the four or
five so-called "norms" that define modern science; and skepticism exercised by
professional colleagues in the form of peer review is widely agreed to have been
one of the main ingredients responsible for the success of modern science. (The
other norms described by Robert Merton [1942], founder of modern sociology of
science, are that knowledge is universal, it is a public good, and scientists should
be disinterested. John Ziman [I9941 considers originality to be a fifth norm.)
A useful dictionary definition of skepticism is, "The doctrine that absolute
knowledge is impossible and that inquiry must be a process of doubting in order
to acquire approximate or relative certainty
. That makes clear immediately
that skepticism is not the same as disbelief. Skepticism views the probability
of a proposition as always less than 1, whereas belief or disbelief are absolute
and assert that the probability equals 1 or 0 respectively.
"Approximate" and "relative" mean that we should always attach to any
given bit of knowledge an estimate of the probability that it is true. Now the
questions become very interesting instead of obvious: How to assign these
probabilities? How to increase them? How much skepticism is the right amount
under which circumstances?
Thus the spirit of skepticism is constructive, it is a means toward improving
knowledge, toward making better estimates of probability. By contrast, belief
and disbelief are destructive-they offer no means toward improving knowledge
because certainty is already being asserted. For example:
Claim Destructive (pseudo) "skepticism" Constructive skepticism
Scientific anomaly.
Extrasensory perception
is real but not (yet?)
reproducible at will.
"Cold fusion": Heavy water
electrolyzed at palladium
generates more heat than
any chemical reaction could;
there must be a nuclear reaction.
Extraordinary claims require
extraordinary proof.
I don't find this evidence in itself
convincing; but here's what
Anecdotes mean nothing.
I
might find convincing: . . .
How to assess the sigmticance of anecdotes?
Can one get any further by assigning
probabilities to each anecdote and
weighting the apparent characteristics
Anything not reproducible
is not scientific.
Absurd. Nuclear reactions can
only occur under conditions
similar to those inside the sun
or inside an atomic bomb. No
matter how deuterium nuclei
fuse, they will always
yield the same products.
of the phenomenon?
Are there ways to study a capricious
phenomenon? Can one create a
statistical framework to do so?
Surface phenomenon or not?
Why so long an incubation period?
Why only palladium?
Try alloys.
Is overvoltage necessary?
If so,
how much? Steady or varying
voltage? If varying, how?
Occam's Razor and Occam's Lobotomy 423
These examples suggest that the distinction between destructive and constructive
skepticism might equally be seen as a distinction between macroskepticism
and micro-skepticism. The destructive criticisms are based on the
large picture, on generalities, on theory; they are deductive. That also makes
them backward-looking. The history of science teaches that all our current
theories are just living on borrowed time. Today's science will tomorrow be
looked back on as benighted superstition, just as we now look back on alchemy,
phlogiston, phrenology, and much else. Even in the 20th century, Nobel Prizes
were awarded for lauded advances in medical science that now seem abhorrent
as well as benighted, for example, seeking to cure schizophrenics by infecting
them with malaria or by cutting out bits of their brains. The question is not
whether today's theories will be superseded, but when and how they will be
superseded. Macro-skeptics-or pseudo-skeptics, as Marcello Truzzi aptly
called them--question whatever seems not to fit with the prevailing scientific
paradigms; they fail to be properly skeptical about contemporary scientific
beliefs.
A common pseudo-skeptical claim is that reliance on current scientific
knowledge, being the simplest explanation, is justified by the philosophical
principle of Occam's Razor. As Jack Good points out (Banks, 1996), that can
become Occam's Lobotomy, trying to oversimplify complex matters; as Einstein
insisted, theories should be as simple as possible, but no simpler.
The crucial weakness in macro-skepticism is its reliance on current theories.
That misunderstands the nature of scientific theories. Theories are never actually
true; or, rather, they can never be known to be true, which amounts to the same
thing (for everyone except metaphysicians, that is). Theories are short-hand
descriptions or classifications of discovered facts and laws, and they are useful
guides to further research. One may legitimately argue as to which theory is
more likely to stimulate productive research; but such arguments are also futile,
because they can only be settled through knowing things that are not yet known.
Fishing is
an often-used analogy here. If you need to feed your family, by all
means cast your nets where you know there are fish, even if the fish are very
small; but there's no need to cast stones or to laugh at the lean fellow next to you
who prefers to stay a bit hungry in the hopes of catching eventually something
really big.
Micro-skepticism is agnosticism as to whether any given claimed anomaly is
the harbinger of a monster of a catch. So it is forward-looking, or at least it is
not backward-looking. Constructive micro-skepticism is skeptical not because
a claim contradicts some theoretical presumption but because it is aware of
the difficulties in acquiring knowledge and looks for loopholes in the offered
evidence; so it safeguards science against Type I errors, against accepting
something that isn't so. Theory-based macro-skepticism does that too, of course,
but it goes too far, leaving itself prone to Type I1 errors, namely, missing
something important. Macro-skeptics never bring about scientific revolutions,
and they resist them to the bitter end.
So much for skepticism as an intellectual approach. But skepticism is not
something abstract, it is exercised by individuals and also in a sense collectively,
by groups of individuals. An approach that may seem intellectually correct
might not always be the most fruitful one in practice, however.
So far as collective skepticism goes, I have already mentioned it as one of the
traditional norms of scientific activity. The need to convince peers, or at least
satisfy them that what one suggests is not absurd, has helped to make what is
published and accepted as "science" more reliable than it would otherwise be.
However, once a discovery has been accepted by the scientific community,
collective skepticism about it is dropped. What Kuhn has called "normal
science" now proceeds just as if this discovery were true for all time. If it
happens to be a substantive fact, such as that the earth is approximately spherical,
no problem; but if it is a law or a theory, then it will, sooner or later, need to
be modified. In the meantime, it acts to suppress other views, including those
that will supersede it in the future. Collective skepticism is now directed, as
usual, only toward challenges of the conventional viewpoint and not toward that
viewpoint itself. And such a stance essentially enthrones macro-skepticism as
the order of the day.
The sin committed perhaps most commonly by reviewers of manuscripts,
and by the editors who let them get away with it, is the deployment of macroskepticism
instead of micro-skepticism. That's what leads people to speak about
a dogmatic Scientific Establishment. That sin is easily slipped into, perhaps even
inevitably. Research has to be guided by something. Normal science is guided
by what is already known, in the expectation that new discoveries will fit in
with current theories. Normal science produces huge amounts of useful data that
benefit many applications of science. So most scientists most of the time are
guided fruitfully in their work by the prevailing paradigm. That is unexceptionable.
But it is one thing to be guided in one's own research by what is already
known; it is quite another thing to block or decry the endeavors of people who
choose to look for
or to pursue anomalies that might presage the next scientific
revolution.
The optimum degree of skepticism is different at different stages of
knowledge-gathering. Small novelties that make no waves are, again appropriately,
regarded with little skepticism, if any. The most significant new
discoveries shake things up and are quite appropriately resisted strongly by the
scientific community, in other words there is a high degree of skepticism about
them. But skepticism should not translate into
suppression.
The scientific community is really a mosaic of small communities, what
Derek Price called "invisible colleges", whose membership is usually of the
order of hundreds. Typically, the invisible colleges trust their peer colleges, so
that once one of them has reached a verdict, it tends to monopolize the whole
scientific community. That is what makes periodicals like Science and
Nature so influential: it is from them that most scientists derive their beliefs
about fields outside their own specialty.
Unfortunately, these so-called "flagship" journals have a very poor record of
appropriate skepticism-insufficient toward people of established reputations,
far too great toward others. Science, for example, rushed into print four articles by
Robert Gallo just as soon as his discovery of HIV had been announced-prior to
peer review-by the Secretary of Health and Human Services. It has taken years
of later investigation to reveal that everything in those papers is untrustworthy
because some of it has been shown to be false (Crewdson, 2002). Even a cursory
reading of those papers makes one wonder how they could have passed competent
peer review, because of their lack of specific detail about crucial experiments
and sources of the most critical biological material. As to rejecting novelties
inappropriately: Paul Lauterbur, who received a Nobel Prize for inventing
MRI (magnetic resonance imaging), had his first paper on that rejected by Nature. He
has suggested that "You could write the entire history of science in the last
50 years in terms of papers rejected by Science or Nature" (Goodspeed, n.d.).
In recent times, a number of people have, apparently independently, come to
recognize that the accepted views on scientific matters of public importance
have become too much shielded from appropriate skepticism; we now have
what
I have called knowledge monopolies and research cartels (Bauer, 2004).
Michael Crichton (2003) has even suggested that whenever we are told that the
scientific consensus is such and such, we should disbelieve it-the appeal to
"everyone knows" being a poor substitute for being shown substantive proof.
James Hogan (2004) has described a number of issues on which the primary
scientific literature is at odds with the officially promulgated view: as to
global warming, DDT, the ozone layer, asbestos, HIVIAIDS, and more. Joel
Kauffman (2006) has demonstrated through careful literature reviews that what
we are told from all quarters is wrong, about aspirin and lowering cholesterol
and greenhouse gases, among other things. But when the inadequacies of these
monopolistic dogmas are pointed out, the dissidents are met with what Edmund
Storms has nicely called pathological skepticism. Skepticism proper, micro-
skepticism, constructive skepticism, is empirical: it looks skeptically
at the evidence, because all observations and experiments are fallible; pathological
skepticism, macro-skepticism, destructive theory-based skepticism, refuses
to look at the evidence because it already knows that the evidence has to
be invalid.
I believe that the greatest danger to good science nowadays is that bureaucracies
fund and control and disseminate science (Bauer, 2004). Bureaucracies
do not practice skepticism of any sort. Individuals may find it hard to admit
error, but it takes a revolution to correct bureaucratic mistakes.
These circumstances make the roles of individuals that much more important.
In a propitious environment, collective norms and collective behavior
can help individuals transcend personal limitations. I believe that individuals
in the military, on the whole, behave more bravely than they might
without the training and discipline afforded by their institution. I believe
whole-ministers and nuns and priests are helped to behave better through
having taken vows.
On the other hand, there can also be environments that bring out the worst,
say, Nazi Germany or the Soviet Union. The traditional norms of science
encouraged scientists to be disinterested, working for the public good,
transcending local attachments, loyal to the universality of scientific truth. But
science has become a highly organized activity, funded and managed through
bureaucracies. As already pointed out, bureaucracies do not practice skepticism
about their own practices. Whistle-blowing may be honored and protected
in principle, but in practice it is hazardous to careers and sometimes to health.
Ombudsman offices are rare, and ombudsman offices with appropriate
autonomy and power are even rarer.
In this environment, the skepticism that science needs, to be reliable and to
progress, depends increasingly on individual actions by individuals who
increasingly need great strength of character and, preferably, private means of
support. They also need to exercise judgment about how much skepticism to
exercise under different circumstances. Toward the conventional wisdom, they
need to direct a general willingness to be skeptical, and they must be open to
specific clues and claims-scientific anomalies-that indicate where skepticism
should be most directed. Of course, they must also direct a somewhat greater
degree of skepticism toward those unorthodox claims-but only microskepticism,
constructive skepticism to help the proponents of the anomalies
see what they must do if they are to become convincing.
However, for that rare person who actually makes a genuinely novel
discovery, skepticism toward that discovery can be counterproductive:
discoverers had better believe strongly in their discovery, had better not be
too skeptical about it, otherwise they might lack the will to carry on in face of
the community's inevitable resistance-resistance that may well come even
from erstwhile colleagues and friends. Forty years ago, Bernard Barber pointed
out that most scientists find themselves at different times on both sides of the
fence, sometimes resisting discoveries by others and sometimes insisting on
discoveries that others are resisting.
As with most things in practice and in life, circumstances alter cases, and all
generalities need to be modified in exceptional cases. Some skepticism is
sometimes good and sometimes bad. Skepticism sometimes serves some people
better than it does others. Judgment is always needed: when to deploy it, and
how much of it.
Notes
Invited presentation at the 24th Annual Meeting of the Society for Scientific
Exploration, Gainesville,
FL, May 2005.
American Heritage Dictionary (3rd ed.), Houghton Mifflin, 1992 (in Microsoft
Bookshelf 1994).
Occam's Razor and Occam's
Lobotomy 427
References
Banks,
D. L. (1996). A conversation with I. J. Good. Statistical Science, 11, 1-19.
Bauer,
H. H. (2004). Science in the 21st century: Knowledge monopolies and research cartels. Journal
of Scientific Exploration, 18,
643-660. 4
Crewdson, J. (2002).
Science Fictions: A Scientific Mystery, a Massive Cover-up, and the Dark
Legacy of Robert Gallo.
Little, Brown.
Crichton, M. (2003).
Aliens cause global warming. Caltech Michelin Lecture, January 17; Available
at:
http://www.crichton-official.com/speeches/speeches~quote04.html.
Goodspeed, M. (n.d.).
Science and the coming dark age. Available at: http://rense.com. Accessed 10
October, 2004.
Hogan, J. (2004).
Kicking the Sacred Cow. Baen.
Kauffman, J. (2006).
Malignant Medical Myths: Why Medical Treatment Causes 200,000 Deaths in
the USA each Year, and How to Protect Yourself.
Infinity.
Merton, R. K. (1942). The normative structure of science. In Storer,
N. W. (Ed.), The Sociology
of Science
(pp. 267-278). University of Chicago Press (1973).
Ziman, J. (1994).
Prometheus Bound: Science in a Dynamic Steady State. Cambridge University
Press.
No comments:
Post a Comment
This blog does NOT allow anonymous comments. All comments are moderated to filter out abusive and vulgar language and any posts indulging in abusive and insulting language shall be deleted without any further discussion.